Some things matter to people. We may be able to
determine the meaning of things and the meaning of information, but information
like “your visa has expired”, or “your academic department has been closed” or
“your daughter has been seriously burnt in an accident” is information which
really matters. The question is, how is this information more significant than
information like “Barack Obama is the president of the United States” or “it is
12 o’clock”? What is it about our apprehension of information which means that
some things we discover make us panic, feel sick, bring relief, or make us
excited? Even information about the time might do this if (say) we have a
deadline to meet. Is it a property of information that it can have this effect?
Can the informing properties be separated from the context of the individual
interpreting it?
How is mattering different from reference? The
problem settles on the extent to which the determining of aboutness is
embodied. Mattering involves the churning of stomach muscles, cramps and other
physical agonies. It causes violence, passion, exuberance. It’s in the guts –
the matter of the body. Meaning, by contrast is largely in the head. The aboutness
of information is selected in brains and stated in conversation. However, meaning
and mattering are related. It is sometimes a surprise to discover that
something really matters to somebody. Their emotional responses will reveal it.
In doing so, they reveal information about the constraints operating on a
person: constraints which are understood because other people have bodies too
and ‘know how it feels’. Mattering is shared – it is the cognition of mutual
constraints.
Meaning creates a dichotomy: what means x also
means that there are things that don’t
mean x. Feelings, on the other hand, are not scarce but abundant: everybody
experiences grief, heartbreak, anxiety, fear. The scarcity that informing
creates can result in the emotional response of things that matter. Daughters, visas,
jobs and deadlines are scarce and so informing of a terrible threat to them is
devastating. More broadly, what Marx describes as ‘alienation’ is precisely the
interface between information and mattering. The rationalisation of capitalist
economy creates scarcity which matters to people: implicit threats to safety,
well-being, housing, security, as well as the creation of new scarce things
which people might covet, are all conveyed by the information of capitalism. The
expression of what matters is suppressed, with a rational alternative offered
whereby mattering is short-circuited by the rationalistic meaning of financial
calculation.
This process of short-circuiting mattering with rationalistic
meaning is also a feature of modern education. The rationalisation of education
has increasingly led to technocracy, where as Horkheimer argues:
“the individual's
self-preservation presupposes his adjustment to the requirements for the
preservation of the system. He no longer has room to evade the system. And just
as the process of rationalization is no longer the result of the anonymous
forces of the market, but is decided in the consciousness of a planning
minority, so the mass of subjects must deliberately adjust themselves: the
subject must, so to speak, devote all his energies to being 'in and of the
movement of things' in the terms of the pragmatistic definition.”
The process in education is well-described by
Andrew Sayer:
“In universities,
research and teaching, as well as a host of other activities, are increasingly
audited, rated and ranked. Teaching comes to be modelled as a rational process
of setting 'learning objectives', deciding how these are to be 'delivered',
designing assessment procedures that test how far students have achieved the
specified 'learning outcomes', as if courses consisted of separable bits of
knowledge or skill that could simply be 'uploaded' by students. The whole
technology is intended to allow the process to be analysed and evaluated.
Teaching is therefore treated much as a production engineer might treat an
industrial process - as capable of being broken down into rationally ordered,
standardized, measurable units, so that wastage and inefficiency can be
identified and eliminated, and quality improved. A general, abstract technology
is thus applied to every course, from aesthetics to zoology. Just what the
learning objectives are apparently does not matter, as long as a rational,
means-ends analysis is used to make sure that they are met. Instead of
seemingly inscrutable processes controlled by unaccountable producers, we have
supposedly rigorous methods for opening the business of education to public
view and comparison.”
The mechanism whereby rationalism supplants
authentic human response towards what matters are poorly understood. Deacon complains
that
“Perhaps the most
tragic feature of our age is that just when we have developed a truly universal
perspective from which to appreciate the vastness of the cosmos, the causal
complexity of material process, and the chemical machinery of life, we hjave at
the same time conceived the realm of value as radically alientated from this
seemingly complete understanding of the fabric of existence. In the natural
sciences there appears to be no place for right/wrong, meaningful/meaningless,
beauty/ugliness, good/evil, love/hate, and so forth. The success of
contemporary science seems to have dethroned the gods and left no foundation
upon which unimpeachable values can rest.”
Deacon’s quest has been to situate value and
concern within more fundamental mechanisms of information. In his philosophy,
it sits as the most evolved aspect of sentience, sitting upon more basic
thermodynamic mechanisms. However, it might be that this hierarchical model of
information is upside-down: that the embodied processes of mattering are where
things start, and that rationalistic information grows from this. For most
teachers, who walk into a classroom and look into the eyes of their students and
read their body language before embarking on quadratic equations, this order of
things may make more sense.
Inverting Deacon’s information means getting to
grips with mattering before getting to grips with reference. Understanding
communications which are effectively without reference is a good starting
point. This is why Alfred Schutz was particularly interested in the way that
music communicates, since, music expresses things which don’t appear to be
about anything (Steven Pinker calls music “cheesecake for the mind” for the
reason), and yet it communicates something which is felt in bodies. Schutz
argues that the musical communication process, whether between composer and
performer, between performers or between audience and performers is one of
mutual appreciation of the flow of inner time and inner life:
“We have therefore the following situation:
two series of events in inner time, one belonging to the stream of
consciousness of the composer, the other to the stream of consciousness of the
beholder, are lived through in simultaneity, which simultaneity is created by
the ongoing flux of the musical process. […] this sharing of the other's flux
of experiences in inner time, this living through a vivid present in common,
constitutes […] the mutual tuning-in relationship, the experience of the
"We," which is at the foundation of all possible communication. The
peculiarity of the musical process of communication consists in the essentially
polythetic character of the communicated content, that is to say, in the fact
that both the flux of the musical events and the activities by which they are
communicated, belong to the dimension of inner time.”
Teaching and learning involves a similar ‘polythetic’
process. Schutz’s description of making music together could equally apply to the
face-to-face environment of the classroom:
“making music
together occurs in a true face-to-face relationship - inasmuch as the
participants are sharing not only a section of time but also a sector of space.
The other's facial expressions, his gestures in handling his instrument, in
short all the activities of performing, gear into the outer world and can be
grasped by the partner in immediacy. Even if performed without communicative
intent, these activities are interpreted by him as indications of what the
other is going to do and therefore as suggestions or even commands for his own
behaviour.”
Musicians (classical at least) must be coordinated
by the codification of the score and rational agreement as to what is to be
done at particular moments. In education, the rational meaning of the curriculum
serves as the framework for the polythetic experiences of the classroom.
Effectively, rational information articulates scarcity: the scarcity of ‘getting
it right’, or being accepted by peers and teachers and so on. The scarcity matters:
it is felt in the body – either through the excitement or elation of being able
to perform the requisite skills or knowledge, or in becoming despondent at the
inability to perform. Teachers notice the body signs. Building the confidence
of a student usually involves using information to declare scarcity which is “less
scarce”. Indeed, it may invoke some kind of shared constraint – something which
binds learners and teachers together; something which is universal or abundant.
Conviviality is a special case of the relationship between meaning and
mattering where the meaning of things is deeply embedded in the shared
understanding of the constraints that bear upon all.
2 comments:
Interesting, I read this post just after reading this:
http://www.theguardian.com/books/2015/mar/21/books-interview-david-graeber-the-utopia-of-rules
And re-reading:
http://strikemag.org/bullshit-jobs/
So much of the modern economy seems to be about hiding information that matters and obscuring activity that has meaning.
Thanks Scott - love the bullshit jobs thing. Graeber's got a lot going on at the moment. His thing on debt on radio 4 is good - http://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/b054zdp6/episodes/player
Post a Comment