I recently attended a wonderful conference on “The Social Philosophy
of Science” at the Russian Academy of Sciences in Moscow. Although this was
entitled “Russian Perspectives”, there were contributions from a number of major
players from the US and UK, including Steve Fuller, Rom Harré (who
unfortunately couldn’t present his paper), Inanna Hatayi-Ataya and Sergio Sismondo. It
was indeed fascinating to compare the Russian contribution to this field which
was always more deeply committed to a social
philosophy of science because of its Marxist foundation.
The conference opened with a Keynote from Steve Fuller about
transformations in the relationship between the public and scientific knowledge
in the light of the web. Fuller was announcing a revolution in the status of
scientists, saying that now as the population could access knowledge and make
their own minds up about things themselves, the authoritarian status of scientist's knowledge was in doubt. Using examples including the L’Aquila earthquake, he
pointed out the difficulties that scientists have in communicating their
science, and how the public will form its own opinion of science. My thoughts
about this were that Fuller’s use of the term science and scientist needs
further inspection. Often, I felt that Fuller was really referring to science
teachers, not scientists. Science teachers are not generally scientists; they
do not engage in inquiry; they are not producing new theories; they are, on the
whole, teaching. However, science teachers often believe themselves to be
scientists. However, they do not believe that the teaching activities they
engage in – the dominant activity – is actually a science worthy of their
attention also. The problem is that ‘authority’ tends to sit in the domain of
the science teacher (indeed, they can often be authoritarian), and not the
scientist. Authority is an aspect of positioning between individuals (Harré’s
Positioning Theory is very valuable here): when one person establishes
themselves as knowing the ‘truth’, there is a parallel process of denying the
claim to legitimate viewpoints by others: “I am the science teacher and you don’t
know anything yet!”. Real scientists, immersed in the cloudy confusion of the
laboratory, tend not to be quite so keen of authority. Their work would see all
participation as a question. So what idea of science is Fuller pursuing here?
Is it the idea of science pertaining to the pursuer of knowledge, or the idea
of science pertaining to the science teacher?
There were some parallels with Sergio Sismondo’s talk about
ontology in Science and Technology studies. Pointing out the tension inherent
in the ‘ontological turn’ in social science between the kind of Nietzschian perspectivism
which denies any kind of objective truth, and the dogmatic and authoritarian
viewpoint about things that are said to exist, Sismondo argued for a view of
multiple ontologies as different ways in which understandings of reality (ontological
perspectives) are enacted on objects and social structures. Arguing
fundamentally that what we end up with is a form of constructivism, his
examples pointed out the different ontological stances of people considered to
be Key Opinion Leaders (KOLs). These people are basically gurus within
professional fields who command high salaries for being experts and attend
different conferences and stay close to a corporate script in promoting a
scientific view in keeping with the corporate objects of their sponsors. Each
enacts their understanding of reality in different ways according to the social
situation they find themselves in.
The central issue here concerns truth. The problem is
whether situations which enact multiple perspectives do not contain within them universal truths. Here, the practices of “the scientist”
as a pursuer of truth is important, and I think distinguishable from the
science teacher, and indeed from the ‘science guru’ of Sismodo’s KOLs. The KOL may
pursue truth in their scientific work, but their engagement by corporations
would lead one to wonder about their intellectual integrity: is empirical
practice separable from social structures? The guru and the teacher have
certain commonalities. The guru may indeed engage in some science, some kind of
inquiry; but they will tend to have to place their inquiry in the back-stage to
their public performances. The guru is beholden to the corporate world as the
teacher is beholden to education. The teacher is bound by responsibilities to
their students and to their institution. What distinguishes these people are
networks of rights, responsibilities and obligations.
I can see two fundamentally different ways of addressing the
issue of truth. There is an argument which articulates by transcendental
reasoning that there must be natural necessity, and causal mechanisms in
nature, where Humean reasoning about causes as constructs is basically wrong. The
implications of this are a materialist and dialectical ontology that sees the
purpose of science as the uncovering and discovery of mechanisms which in turn
have a bearing on social structures. True work = true mechanisms.
Alternatively, there is a view that Hume was right, that there is no natural
necessity, that causes are not real, but that truth is real and revealed
through the encounter between being and event. This is basically the position
of Badiou and those subscribing to the loose school of “speculative realists”. This
position also articulates a dialectical process whereby political action is
directly connected to logical revelation of truth, and where science and
mathematics serves truth by comprehending the natural ordering of the social. Whilst
each position’s ontological stance is impossible to prove, both positions end
up in the same place: with the political.
I found myself reflecting on this in Inanna Hamati-Ataya talk on the relationship between empirical practice and social structure. Inanna gave a talk about ontology and post-foundationalism in science studies. She argued for a position which situates empiricism in relation to politics and society to which I am sympathetic. However, I raised the question about the importance of not throwing out empiricism. She replied that she was after a more pluralistic conception of science and methodology. What interests me about this is for all the ontological belly-aching that goes on in social science (particularly arguing for natural necessity or contingency) the ontological position appears to oscillate around central principles:
- Whether contingency of necessity of nature is the case or not cannot be established beyond doubt. It is not a matter that can be settled by transcendental argument (as I once thought, having pursued a critical realist path). Coherent transcendental arguments can present both necessity and contingency as possibilities (it is the difference between Bhaskar and Badiou)
- However, when we ask “what matters?” the answer always is simple: we have to look after each other.
Inanna’s conclusion is right; however, I think this conclusion can be reached from a deeper engagement with empirical practice - particularly about what we consider to be empiricism as that practice which entwines expectation and explanation.
Moving on to more practical ground, I was very struck by a fascinating presentation by Maria Bereznyak on the transliteration and translation of scientific terminology between the west and Russia, and between Russia and China. "What about cybernetics?" I thought. Indeed, for the more practically useful aspects of scientific inquiry (and cybernetics is one of those), there are more immediate problems concerning communication amongst scientists than ontological concerns. Indeed, the fact of difficulties in communication between Chinese, Russian and Western scientists is perhaps more real than any of this stuff! What would the Chinese do with cybernetics if they knew the literature?
Moving on to more practical ground, I was very struck by a fascinating presentation by Maria Bereznyak on the transliteration and translation of scientific terminology between the west and Russia, and between Russia and China. "What about cybernetics?" I thought. Indeed, for the more practically useful aspects of scientific inquiry (and cybernetics is one of those), there are more immediate problems concerning communication amongst scientists than ontological concerns. Indeed, the fact of difficulties in communication between Chinese, Russian and Western scientists is perhaps more real than any of this stuff! What would the Chinese do with cybernetics if they knew the literature?
And finally, having been immersed in all this talk of ontology, I learnt on the way home of the death of Roy Bhaskar. That's perhaps a cause for deeper reflection on the issues of natural necessity, but also about the contribution of a philosopher who has had a bigger impact on my own development than anybody else.
No comments:
Post a Comment